Wittgenstein's Diagonal Argument: A Variation on Cantor and Turing
Turing was a philosopher of logic and mathematics, as well as a mathematician. His work throughout his life owed much to the Cambridge milieu in which he was educated and to which he returned throughout his life. A rich and distinctive tradition discussing how the notion of “common sense” relates t...
Main Authors: | , |
---|---|
Format: | Article |
Language: | English |
Published: |
Disputatio Editions-IAR
2019-06-01
|
Series: | Disputatio |
Subjects: | |
Online Access: | https://studiahumanitatis.eu/ojs/index.php/disputatio/article/view/158 |
id |
doaj-821d514302914897bbfb08090e27b17f |
---|---|
record_format |
Article |
spelling |
doaj-821d514302914897bbfb08090e27b17f2021-09-13T11:27:16ZengDisputatio Editions-IARDisputatio2254-06012019-06-018910.5281/zenodo.3568216Wittgenstein's Diagonal Argument: A Variation on Cantor and TuringJuliet Floyd0Kurt Wischin1Boston University, United States of AmericaUniversidad de Granada, Spain Turing was a philosopher of logic and mathematics, as well as a mathematician. His work throughout his life owed much to the Cambridge milieu in which he was educated and to which he returned throughout his life. A rich and distinctive tradition discussing how the notion of “common sense” relates to the foundations of logic was being developed during Turing’s undergraduate days, most intensively by Wittgenstein, whose exchanges with Russell, Ramsey, Sraffa, Hardy, Littlewood and others formed part of the backdrop which shaped Turing’s work. Beginning with a Moral Sciences Club talk in 1933, Turing developed an “anthropological” approach to the foundations of logic, influenced by Wittgenstein, in which “common sense” plays a foundational role. This may be seen not only in “On Computable Numbers” (1936/7) and Turing’s dissertation (written 1938, see (1939)), but in his exchanges with Wittgenstein in 1939 and in two later papers, “The Reform of Mathematical Phraseology and Notation” (1944/5) and “Solvable and Unsolvable Problems” (1954). https://studiahumanitatis.eu/ojs/index.php/disputatio/article/view/158Common SenseFormal SystemTuring MachineOrdinary LanguagePhilosophical Discussion |
collection |
DOAJ |
language |
English |
format |
Article |
sources |
DOAJ |
author |
Juliet Floyd Kurt Wischin |
spellingShingle |
Juliet Floyd Kurt Wischin Wittgenstein's Diagonal Argument: A Variation on Cantor and Turing Disputatio Common Sense Formal System Turing Machine Ordinary Language Philosophical Discussion |
author_facet |
Juliet Floyd Kurt Wischin |
author_sort |
Juliet Floyd |
title |
Wittgenstein's Diagonal Argument: A Variation on Cantor and Turing |
title_short |
Wittgenstein's Diagonal Argument: A Variation on Cantor and Turing |
title_full |
Wittgenstein's Diagonal Argument: A Variation on Cantor and Turing |
title_fullStr |
Wittgenstein's Diagonal Argument: A Variation on Cantor and Turing |
title_full_unstemmed |
Wittgenstein's Diagonal Argument: A Variation on Cantor and Turing |
title_sort |
wittgenstein's diagonal argument: a variation on cantor and turing |
publisher |
Disputatio Editions-IAR |
series |
Disputatio |
issn |
2254-0601 |
publishDate |
2019-06-01 |
description |
Turing was a philosopher of logic and mathematics, as well as a mathematician. His work throughout his life owed much to the Cambridge milieu in which he was educated and to which he returned throughout his life. A rich and distinctive tradition discussing how the notion of “common sense” relates to the foundations of logic was being developed during Turing’s undergraduate days, most intensively by Wittgenstein, whose exchanges with Russell, Ramsey, Sraffa, Hardy, Littlewood and others formed part of the backdrop which shaped Turing’s work. Beginning with a Moral Sciences Club talk in 1933, Turing developed an “anthropological” approach to the foundations of logic, influenced by Wittgenstein, in which “common sense” plays a foundational role. This may be seen not only in “On Computable Numbers” (1936/7) and Turing’s dissertation (written 1938, see (1939)), but in his exchanges with Wittgenstein in 1939 and in two later papers, “The Reform of Mathematical Phraseology and Notation” (1944/5) and “Solvable and Unsolvable Problems” (1954).
|
topic |
Common Sense Formal System Turing Machine Ordinary Language Philosophical Discussion |
url |
https://studiahumanitatis.eu/ojs/index.php/disputatio/article/view/158 |
work_keys_str_mv |
AT julietfloyd wittgensteinsdiagonalargumentavariationoncantorandturing AT kurtwischin wittgensteinsdiagonalargumentavariationoncantorandturing |
_version_ |
1717381032249917440 |