Wittgenstein's Diagonal Argument: A Variation on Cantor and Turing

Turing was a philosopher of logic and mathematics, as well as a mathematician. His work throughout his life owed much to the Cambridge milieu in which he was educated and to which he returned throughout his life. A rich and distinctive tradition discussing how the notion of “common sense” relates t...

Full description

Bibliographic Details
Main Authors: Juliet Floyd, Kurt Wischin
Format: Article
Language:English
Published: Disputatio Editions-IAR 2019-06-01
Series:Disputatio
Subjects:
Online Access:https://studiahumanitatis.eu/ojs/index.php/disputatio/article/view/158
id doaj-821d514302914897bbfb08090e27b17f
record_format Article
spelling doaj-821d514302914897bbfb08090e27b17f2021-09-13T11:27:16ZengDisputatio Editions-IARDisputatio2254-06012019-06-018910.5281/zenodo.3568216Wittgenstein's Diagonal Argument: A Variation on Cantor and TuringJuliet Floyd0Kurt Wischin1Boston University, United States of AmericaUniversidad de Granada, Spain Turing was a philosopher of logic and mathematics, as well as a mathematician. His work throughout his life owed much to the Cambridge milieu in which he was educated and to which he returned throughout his life. A rich and distinctive tradition discussing how the notion of “common sense” relates to the foundations of logic was being developed during Turing’s undergraduate days, most intensively by Wittgenstein, whose exchanges with Russell, Ramsey, Sraffa, Hardy, Littlewood and others formed part of the backdrop which shaped Turing’s work. Beginning with a Moral Sciences Club talk in 1933, Turing developed an “anthropological” approach to the foundations of logic, influenced by Wittgenstein, in which “common sense” plays a foundational role. This may be seen not only in “On Computable Numbers” (1936/7) and Turing’s dissertation (written 1938, see (1939)), but in his exchanges with Wittgenstein in 1939 and in two later papers, “The Reform of Mathematical Phraseology and Notation” (1944/5) and “Solvable and Unsolvable Problems” (1954). https://studiahumanitatis.eu/ojs/index.php/disputatio/article/view/158Common SenseFormal SystemTuring MachineOrdinary LanguagePhilosophical Discussion
collection DOAJ
language English
format Article
sources DOAJ
author Juliet Floyd
Kurt Wischin
spellingShingle Juliet Floyd
Kurt Wischin
Wittgenstein's Diagonal Argument: A Variation on Cantor and Turing
Disputatio
Common Sense
Formal System
Turing Machine
Ordinary Language
Philosophical Discussion
author_facet Juliet Floyd
Kurt Wischin
author_sort Juliet Floyd
title Wittgenstein's Diagonal Argument: A Variation on Cantor and Turing
title_short Wittgenstein's Diagonal Argument: A Variation on Cantor and Turing
title_full Wittgenstein's Diagonal Argument: A Variation on Cantor and Turing
title_fullStr Wittgenstein's Diagonal Argument: A Variation on Cantor and Turing
title_full_unstemmed Wittgenstein's Diagonal Argument: A Variation on Cantor and Turing
title_sort wittgenstein's diagonal argument: a variation on cantor and turing
publisher Disputatio Editions-IAR
series Disputatio
issn 2254-0601
publishDate 2019-06-01
description Turing was a philosopher of logic and mathematics, as well as a mathematician. His work throughout his life owed much to the Cambridge milieu in which he was educated and to which he returned throughout his life. A rich and distinctive tradition discussing how the notion of “common sense” relates to the foundations of logic was being developed during Turing’s undergraduate days, most intensively by Wittgenstein, whose exchanges with Russell, Ramsey, Sraffa, Hardy, Littlewood and others formed part of the backdrop which shaped Turing’s work. Beginning with a Moral Sciences Club talk in 1933, Turing developed an “anthropological” approach to the foundations of logic, influenced by Wittgenstein, in which “common sense” plays a foundational role. This may be seen not only in “On Computable Numbers” (1936/7) and Turing’s dissertation (written 1938, see (1939)), but in his exchanges with Wittgenstein in 1939 and in two later papers, “The Reform of Mathematical Phraseology and Notation” (1944/5) and “Solvable and Unsolvable Problems” (1954).
topic Common Sense
Formal System
Turing Machine
Ordinary Language
Philosophical Discussion
url https://studiahumanitatis.eu/ojs/index.php/disputatio/article/view/158
work_keys_str_mv AT julietfloyd wittgensteinsdiagonalargumentavariationoncantorandturing
AT kurtwischin wittgensteinsdiagonalargumentavariationoncantorandturing
_version_ 1717381032249917440