How do you know that? Automatic belief inferences in passing conversation

There is an ongoing debate, both in philosophy and psychology, as to whether people are able to automatically infer what others may know, or whether they can only derive belief inferences by deploying cognitive resources. Evidence from laboratory tasks, often involving false beliefs or visual-perspe...

Full description

Bibliographic Details
Main Authors: Gibson, E. (Author), Mollica, F. (Author), Oraa Ali, M. (Author), Rubio-Fernández, P. (Author)
Format: Article
Language:English
Published: Elsevier B.V. 2019
Subjects:
Online Access:View Fulltext in Publisher
LEADER 02782nam a2200613Ia 4500
001 10.1016-j.cognition.2019.104011
008 220511s2019 CNT 000 0 und d
020 |a 00100277 (ISSN) 
245 1 0 |a How do you know that? Automatic belief inferences in passing conversation 
260 0 |b Elsevier B.V.  |c 2019 
856 |z View Fulltext in Publisher  |u https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2019.104011 
520 3 |a There is an ongoing debate, both in philosophy and psychology, as to whether people are able to automatically infer what others may know, or whether they can only derive belief inferences by deploying cognitive resources. Evidence from laboratory tasks, often involving false beliefs or visual-perspective taking, has suggested that belief inferences are cognitively costly, controlled processes. Here we suggest that in everyday conversation, belief reasoning is pervasive and therefore potentially automatic in some cases. To test this hypothesis, we conducted two pre-registered self-paced reading experiments (N1 = 91, N2 = 89). The results of these experiments showed that participants slowed down when a stranger commented ‘That greasy food is bad for your ulcer’ relative to conditions where a stranger commented on their own ulcer or a friend made either comment – none of which violated participants’ common-ground expectations. We conclude that Theory of Mind models need to account for belief reasoning in conversation as it is at the center of everyday social interaction. © 2019 Elsevier B.V. 
650 0 4 |a adult 
650 0 4 |a Adult 
650 0 4 |a Article 
650 0 4 |a attention 
650 0 4 |a Automatic and controlled processes 
650 0 4 |a Belief inferences 
650 0 4 |a cognition 
650 0 4 |a comprehension 
650 0 4 |a conversation 
650 0 4 |a False-belief tasks 
650 0 4 |a human 
650 0 4 |a human experiment 
650 0 4 |a human relation 
650 0 4 |a Humans 
650 0 4 |a interpersonal communication 
650 0 4 |a Interpersonal Relations 
650 0 4 |a knowledge 
650 0 4 |a motivation 
650 0 4 |a perception 
650 0 4 |a physiology 
650 0 4 |a pilot study 
650 0 4 |a Pragmatics 
650 0 4 |a priority journal 
650 0 4 |a reading 
650 0 4 |a Reading 
650 0 4 |a self concept 
650 0 4 |a self report 
650 0 4 |a social belief 
650 0 4 |a social cognition 
650 0 4 |a social interaction 
650 0 4 |a Social Perception 
650 0 4 |a theory of mind 
650 0 4 |a theory of mind 
650 0 4 |a Theory of Mind 
650 0 4 |a Theory of Mind 
650 0 4 |a thinking 
650 0 4 |a Thinking 
700 1 |a Gibson, E.  |e author 
700 1 |a Mollica, F.  |e author 
700 1 |a Oraa Ali, M.  |e author 
700 1 |a Rubio-Fernández, P.  |e author 
773 |t Cognition